aristotle

In which Leo Strauss and Jeremy Bentham encounter the ghost of Aristotle by Nathan Jones

Hilary Putnam’s Truth, Reason, and History (itself an excursion prompted by Richard Rorty’s Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature) sent me down the rabbit-hole of investigating the life and thought of arch-utilitarian, Jeremy Bentham. (For context, see my previous post, which includes a lengthy quotation from Putnam that touches on Bentham and Bernard Williams.) I was intrigued to learn (from the Libertarians, no less!) that Bentham was highly critical of natural rights, which he considered to be pernicious fictions promoted by revolutionaries to subvert law and order.

With Natural Right and History by Leo Strauss in mind, and as part of my exploration of large language models in the service of a Langara College working group on generative AI, I decided it would be fun to set a creative test for Microsoft’s “AI companion,” Copilot, in this philosophical context.

PROMPT: Develop a Platonic dialog between Jeremy Bentham and Leo Strauss on the topic of natural right. Interrupt this dialog at an appropriate juncture with an appearance by the ghost of Aristotle, who changes the course of the conversation with his view on the role of government in enforcing natural rights.

RESPONSE:

A Platonic Dialogue between Jeremy Bentham and Leo Strauss on Natural Right

Characters:

  • Jeremy Bentham (B)

  • Leo Strauss (S)

  • Ghost of Aristotle (A)

Setting: A quiet garden in an academic institution, where Bentham and Strauss meet to discuss their views on natural right.

B: Good day, Mr. Strauss. I understand you have some strong views on natural right. I must say, I find the concept rather perplexing and, dare I say, nonsensical.

S: Good day, Mr. Bentham. Indeed, I do hold natural right in high regard. It is a concept deeply rooted in the rational order of nature, as understood by the ancients.

B: Ah, the ancients. You mean those who believed in inherent rights bestowed by nature? I find such notions to be mere fictions, invented to justify rebellion and anarchy. Rights, in my view, are the creations of legal systems, not nature.

S: I see where you are coming from. However, I believe that natural right, as conceived by philosophers like Plato and Aristotle, is not about anarchy but about understanding the rational order of the world. It provides a framework for justice that transcends positive law.

B: But how can we base our moral and legal systems on something so abstract and variable? Natural rights are, as I have said, “nonsense upon stilts.” They lack the concrete foundation that legal rights possess.

S: Natural right, Mr. Bentham, is not as abstract as you might think. It is about recognizing a hierarchy of ends that are universally valid, even if the specific rules of action to achieve these ends can vary with circumstances. This flexibility is what makes natural right adaptable to different contexts.

B: Flexibility, you say? To me, that sounds like a recipe for inconsistency and confusion. How can we ensure justice if our moral principles are so malleable?

S: The flexibility of natural right does not imply inconsistency. Rather, it acknowledges the complexity of human life and the need for moral principles that can adapt to different situations. Unlike the rigid rules of natural law, natural right allows for a more nuanced approach to justice.

B: I remain unconvinced. My utilitarian approach focuses on the greatest happiness for the greatest number, a clear and measurable goal. Natural right, with its talk of hierarchies and ends, seems too nebulous to guide practical decision-making.

S: Utilitarianism, while pragmatic, often overlooks the deeper values and commitments that define human life. Natural right, as I see it, provides a richer moral framework that respects these values. It is not merely about outcomes but about the principles that guide our actions.

B: Principles are all well and good, but without concrete outcomes, they are of little use. My concern is with the tangible effects of our actions on human happiness.

S: And that is where we differ, Mr. Bentham. While I do not dismiss the importance of outcomes, I believe that a focus solely on consequences can lead to a neglect of the moral integrity and the deeper purposes that give life meaning.

B: Perhaps we shall have to agree to disagree. Your natural right remains, to me, an elegant but impractical ideal.

S: And your utilitarianism, Mr. Bentham, while practical, may sometimes miss the profound truths about human nature and justice. But such is the beauty of philosophical discourse—we challenge and refine each other’s views.

B: Indeed, Mr. Strauss. It has been a stimulating conversation. Until next time.

S: Until next time, Mr. Bentham.

(Suddenly, a ghostly figure appears, interrupting their conversation.)

A: Gentlemen, I could not help but overhear your discussion. I am Aristotle, and I have come to offer my perspective on the role of government in enforcing natural rights.

B: Aristotle! This is quite unexpected. Please, enlighten us with your wisdom.

S: Indeed, Aristotle. Your views on natural right and the role of the polis are most welcome.

A: Thank you. In my view, the role of government is to cultivate virtue and ensure the good life for its citizens. Natural rights are not merely abstract principles but are grounded in the nature of human beings as rational and social creatures. The government must create conditions that allow individuals to fulfill their potential and achieve eudaimonia, or flourishing.

B: But how does this translate into practical governance? How can a government enforce such lofty ideals?

A: The government must enact laws that promote justice and the common good. These laws should be based on the natural order and the rational nature of human beings. It is through the enforcement of just laws that the government can protect natural rights and ensure that citizens live virtuous lives.

S: This aligns with my view that natural right involves a hierarchy of ends. The government must recognize and uphold these ends to create a just society.

B: I see. So, you believe that the government’s role is to enforce laws that reflect the natural order and promote human flourishing?

A: Precisely. The laws must be just and aligned with the rational nature of human beings. This is how the government can protect natural rights and ensure the well-being of its citizens.

S: Thank you, Aristotle. Your insights have added a valuable dimension to our discussion.

B: Indeed, Aristotle. Your perspective has given me much to consider. Perhaps there is more to natural right than I initially thought.

A: I am glad to have contributed to your understanding. Remember, the pursuit of wisdom is a lifelong journey. Farewell, gentlemen.

(The ghost of Aristotle fades away, leaving Bentham and Strauss deep in thought.)